| ||||||||||||||
An Open Market for Human
Organs By Daniel Freeman When the practice of financially
compensating individuals for the sale and purchase of human organs
first came to light several years ago, it aroused such public horror
and outrage that most professional medical associations denounced it
and nearly every country made it illegal. It is acceptable and even
admirable for someone to voluntarily donate an organ to help another
person. However, the
current belief is that it is morally wrong to exchange human organs
for cash. In addition,
it is immoral in our society to use money to entice someone to have
a major operation to remove a vital organ for the benefit of another
human being. This paper
outlines the rationale for reopening and re-evaluating the currently
closed debate over the permissible legitimacy of selling and
purchasing human organs. Extraordinary technological advances
in science and medicine, which include successful lifesaving
transplantation of human tissues, provide immeasurable social
benefits.
Unfortunately, profound implications involving autonomy and
belonging, as well as opposing moral conditions and legal concerns,
have made the sale and purchase of human organs illegal. Currently, the “sale of any
human tissue is prohibited by law in the United States” (Futterman
165).1 The
current policy of voluntary organ donation is inadequate, flawed,
and unfair. People
should be allowed to sell their organs, which under current law they
are only allowed to voluntarily donate without
compensation. Organ transplant surgery has
drastically improved the health, quality of life, and life
expectancy of many people whose organs have failed. Over 200,000 people a year
receive transplants that improve their lives (Dowie
121).2 Among
the parts of the body that can be replaced are the inner ear, the
cornea, glands (pancreas, pituitary, and thyroid), blood vessels,
tendons, cartilage, muscles, testicles, ovaries, fallopian tubes,
nerves, skin, bone marrow, blood, liver, kidney, lungs, and
heart.
When an individual’s organ shuts
down, his quality of life, and even possibility of life,
dramatically decreases.
A new transplanted organ could make the difference between
life and death. If a
person’s heart shuts down, medical science has the ability to save
that person’s life by providing a new heart (Mabie
52).3 In the
last two decades of technological breakthroughs in heart
transplants, survival rates have improved enormously to over 90%
from only 67% in 1981.
With over 2,000 heart transplants each year almost all of the
patients survive, whereas without the surgery they face almost
certain death (Kittrege 14).4 Many people also receive
liver or lung transplants as well. Liver transplants are
successful over 80% of the time and lung transplants are successful
over 70% of the time.
One patient in 1985 received both a heart and a lung
transplant and is still alive (Kittrege 14).5 While the surgeries have
become increasingly successful, so have the needs. Transplantation centers
“working with organs other than kidneys indicate that eventually
there will be a need for over 10,000 heart transplants, 5,000-10,000
liver transplants, and the same number of pancreas transplants
annually” (Leinwand 38).6 The last three decades have
witnessed great medical advances in the field of transplants and
implants, and now through the miracle of organ transplantation,
lifesaving feats previously only dreamed of are being performed
every day. Currently, there is a shortage of
organs available to people that could benefit greatly from
them. Like any other
good or service that is in demand, a market for human organs would
thrive and efficiently allocate organs to those most in need. Today, from a supply
standpoint, most organ donation decisions are made at the Department
of Motor Vehicles, where one can check a box whether or not he wants
to donate organs in the case of a fatal car accident. There is also an
organ/tissue donor card one can fill out, informing one’s
family of his desire to be a donor in the event of death. Still, there remains a
massive shortage of organs.
Why is this? It's simple. Neither donors nor their
families are being paid one penny. People often have to wait on
endless wait lists for organs, and do not receive their organs in
time. Despite the extremely beneficial
technological advances and success rates of the transplants, most
people are still unable to enjoy the benefits of a transplant
because of a lack of organs to be transplanted. People cannot have an organ
transplanted if a suitable organ is not available. Clearly, there is “an
extreme shortage of donor organs” (Evans 234).7 Under the current system
where there is an obvious shortage, the distribution of the organs
is very unfair as well.
Only a small percentage of people who need the organs are
able to get them. For
the most part, the people who are most likely to receive organs are
those with influential families that capture media attention (Capron
414).8 This
is very unfair.
Receiving an organ is hard enough in the first place even for
those from influential families. For those that are not from
influential families, obtaining a crucial organ is highly unlikely,
and nearly impossible.
The current system is flawed and unfair. Some kind of action must be taken to
help the urgent search for donors (Heintze 86-87).9 People who need organs line
up to get them and often never receive them, because the demand for
organs far exceeds the supply.
The problem is that there are insufficient numbers of organs
potentially suitable for transplantation, leaving those waiting for
the organ to improve their quality of life or even to save their
life still waiting. A
sufficient supply of organs that could “meet current needs does not
appear feasible within the present voluntary or request-for-consent
framework” (Futterman 162).10 Under economic theory, when
demand exceeds the quantity supplied then supply must increase. Undisputedly, right now
there are “not enough organs to go around” (Gutkind
233).11
Therefore under economic theory, a change must occur to cause
the supply to increase to match the demand. To an economist, the major
reason for the imbalance between demand and supply of organs is that
the United States and practically all other countries forbid the
purchase and sale of organs.
This means that under present laws, people give their organs
to be used after they die, or often in the case of kidneys and liver
lobes, while alive, only out of altruism and similar motives. In fact, practically all
transplants of kidneys and liver lobes with live donors are from one
family member to another member. The current system of voluntary organ
donation has proven to be very limited. Considerable “problems in
the policy permit a significant number of patients to die in
hospitals” (Futterman 163).12 The well-known shortage of
organs for transplantation causes much suffering and death. Dialysis (the alternative to
a new kidney), a wretched experience for most patients, is rationed
in most places and is unavailable to most patients. The prohibition of organ
sales excludes organs that would otherwise be available. Since it is clear that a
change must occur to affect the supply for the better, a possible
solution to giving people an incentive to donate those crucial and
extremely beneficial organs would be to offer monetary and
non-monetary rewards for organs. Allowing people to sell their organs instead of
merely donating them would encourage more people to give up their
organs, resulting in a much larger supply of available organs. The current critical
question is “how the public can be encouraged to supply organs to
meet the needs of waiting recipients?” (Kutner
23).13 A
very legitimate solution would be to allow people to sell their
organs. Legalizing
organ sales would save many people’s lives, discourage a black
market, reduce government expenses, compensate the donors and
protect an individual’s right to choose. Foremost, legalizing organ
sales will save people's lives. We must ask ourselves what
could be more important than saving people's lives. There is no reason for
people to die if society provides the means to save
them. If laws were changed so that organs
could be purchased and sold, some people would give not only out of
altruism, but for financial gain as well. The result would be an
increased supply of available organs. In a free market, the price
of organs for transplants would settle at levels that would
eliminate the excess demand for each type of organ. Logically, living people are
inclined to not want to give up their organ no matter what. On top of that, they must
undergo painful surgery to have their organ removed. Very few people in their
right mind would want to go through the pain and trouble of having
an organ removed even if it meant saving the life of a loved
one. If donating even
to a loved one is that unappealing, then deciding to donate an organ
to a complete stranger with no reward is absolutely absurd. For example, a woman might
give her kidney to her child, but if asked to donate one to a
stranger she would probably recoil at the obvious costs: loss of a
kidney, the pain of surgery, the long recovery, some diminished
physical capacity, and the risk of death. Although the stranger’s need
for the kidney is just as real and urgent as the need the woman’s
child has, few in their right mind would endure the pain and agony
merely to be nice.
However, many more people would be inclined to help the
community by giving up their organs while still alive or by donating
them after they die, if they knew they or their families would be
compensated. Another benefit can be appreciated if
we ask questions about the optimal way to die. When a person dies, he cannot
take his wealth with him.
Generally, the individual’s wealth is passed on to his
heirs. The same
principal applies to organs.
If one cannot take his organs with him, why not leave them to
someone who could really benefit from them? The supply of organs has
depended on people's benevolence, and benevolence hasn't been
enough. If people don't
see a gain for themselves or their families in giving up body parts,
they often don't. But
if they can sell their organs at death and pass the financial
benefit on to loved ones, they suddenly have a strong incentive for
making sure that they have filled out all the right forms before
dying. Being able to
sell their body parts is like being given a substantial life
insurance policy for free. Most transplantable organs, however,
are "harvested" from cadavers, and indeed many organs, including
livers, hearts, and lungs, can only be obtained from persons who are
deceased. One important
reason for this low donation rate is that relatively few individuals
fill out and carry organ donor cards or otherwise indicate their
willingness to donate their organs prior to death. Purchasing organs from dead
people is obviously impossible. It also seems unwise to seek to
purchase the rights to a person's organs while they are awaiting
death: such transactions would often be traumatic for all concerned,
and patients might be worried that if they agreed to sell, the care
they received subsequently would be less than zealous. It has been seriously
proposed, even by individuals who express strong opposition in the
abstract to the idea of compensating organ donors, that organ
procurement agencies offer to pay funeral expenses for poor families
if they will agree to donate the organs of a deceased relative. Without adequate financial
compensation, there is clearly little incentive for the family of
the deceased to donate the organs. However, many people would
gladly agree to sell their body parts after they die, knowing their
families would benefit financially. It would be part of the
deceased’s estate for his heirs, or a type of insurance policy his
heirs would inherit. In
addition, the burden of making this decision would not be left to
the family of the deceased. Life insurance companies would be
natural purchasers of such a system because these companies are
already involved in the types of actuarial calculations and
financial transactions that would be involved. Insurers might simply insert
in their annual premium statements a provision (a check-off box
would probably suffice) by means of which their policyholders could
indicate that, in the event they were to die during the period
(generally the coming year) covered by the premium statement, the
insurance company or its assignees would have the right to harvest
any of the insured's organs that were transplantable. In return for checking this
box, the insured would receive a specified reduction in their
insurance premium for that period and share in the financial
profit. Individuals
would be free to change their mind about being a donor annually (or
whenever their insurance policy was renewed). Cash or another form of compensation
could move us toward the desired outcome of saving more lives. Society recognizes people’s
autonomy by permitting them to make their decisions and take their
risks. Society
acknowledges their right to decide what is done to their
bodies. As long as
their choice is informed, the decision to donate an organ is morally
legitimate, even praiseworthy.
The same criteria that supports allowing people to donate an
organ also supports allowing them to sell one. When healthy and competent
adults want money to meet the medical needs of a family member or of
themselves, they should be allowed to receive compensation for
donating an organ.
Paying donors should not be done in a private transaction,
but in an open market.
The exchange of an organ for money should be orchestrated by
a specific organization where the fee is set by a panel of
experts. Allowing people to sell their organs
would improve the quality of life for both the receiver of the organ
as well as the seller of the organ. If people were compensated
for donating an organ, it is conceivable and likely that more people
would be willing to undergo the inconvenience of donating an organ
than there are today.
For example, in 1983, a man tried to sell a kidney for
$25,000. His intentions
were to use the money for purchasing a fast-food restaurant (Weiss
17).14 This
man’s kidney transaction (if it was allowed to take place) would
have been quite beneficial to both parties, while at the same time
harming nobody. He
(after being quite informed) decided that he did not need both of
his kidneys. His second
kidney might be better suited and more appreciated by a person that
is in need of a kidney transplant. By giving up his extra
(spare) kidney, this man would have been able to save the life of
another person, and life is considered priceless. To compensate for his lost
time and for the inconvenience of the surgery, the man wanted some
money in exchange. He
did not ask for a fortune that would completely wipe out the
financial situation of the family. He simply asked for enough
money so that he could get his fast-food restaurant underway. If the man was able to
receive his payment (clearly a nice price to both parties), then he
would have been able to start his business, improving his quality of life as
well. After close
examination, the organ sale benefits both parties while at the same
time leaving nobody harmed.
What is the problem?
Implementing a system where “donation is no longer perceived
as burdensome may result in more positive donation interactions and
fewer wasted organs” (Futterman 168).15 It is society’s
responsibility to look after people’s lives and have everyone’s best
interest at heart.
Currently, looking out for everyone’s best interest means
changing the current wasteful system, in which too many usable
lifesaving organs are wasted.
The need for transplanted organs is
undeniable and “more than once it has been noted that over 8,000
people in the United States who die from renal failure might have
been saved by a kidney transplant” (Perry 64).16 Although altruism can be a
powerful factor in motivating organ donations, it works best within
families and cannot be expected to function as efficiently in the
market. Thus, to
increase supply, it is necessary to provide families with additional
incentives. To increase
donations, financial incentives must be considered. Although a world in which
100 individuals each has one kidney is a world with higher expected
benefits than a world in which 50 people each have 2 kidneys the
other 50 people have failing kidneys and face dialysis or death,
there are many ethical dilemmas in such a
system.
Some claim that organ sales must be banned because
individuals verge on irrationality, unable to make informed
judgments about the risk that they assume. However, complex surgery
tests rational decision making as well (and that is not
banned). Live organ
donations are not banned either, and those may put enormous pressure
on a member of the family to make an uncompensated transfer. To further reduce the risk,
potential donors could be given information and independent
advice. Banning a
practice as a result of potential confusion and pressure cannot be
justified. Although
most potential sellers would probably decline to offer an organ for
sale even if it were legal, universal participation is not needed to
erase the shortfall in available organs; only a tiny fraction of the
population is needed to participate. More thoughtful critics suggest that
allowing organs to be bought and sold might actually reduce the
total number of organs available for transplants because they claim
it would sufficiently lower the number of organs donated from
altruistic motives to dominate the increase due to those sold
commercially (Childress 69-70).17 They claim that “any sales
of organs will drive out voluntary donations, and do nothing to
alleviate the present shortage” (Epstein 66).18 However, it is unlikely that
such would be the case where “all donors would want cash, but even
if they did, the dangers of organ sales to the procurement process
are hard to detect” (Epstein 66).19 Presently, only a small
fraction of potentially useable organs are available for
transplants.
Compensating people either for allowing their organs to be
used after their death, or for donating their kidneys and liver
lobes while they are alive would enormously widen the scope of the
potential organ market. Additionally, there is currently a
large black market in which organs are being sold anyway. Although clearly against the
law, many people still sell their organs, but just do it under the
radar. Right now,
transplant centers “pave the way for the sale of transplantation
services from $100,000 and up.
But it is the doctors and transplant centers that implicitly
capture the proceeds from sale” (Epstein 66).20 Legalizing the sales would
not increase the bill to the recipients. Instead, the party that
donated the organ would be able to receive a portion of the gain
(Epstein 66).21
An open market in organs would sharply curtail the present
black market where some people in need of transplants have them in
poorer countries where enforcement against selling organs is
slack. Since the
quality of the surgeons and hospitals in these countries is much
lower than in advanced countries, this often greatly reduces the
quality of the organs used and how well they are matched to the
organ types of recipients.
It can be assumed that most patients want to have their
transplant operation done in the safest manner. Transplant operations must
be safe for everyone, so that nobody has to suffer. In order to be safe, organs
must be tested and inspected carefully before being
transplanted. By
legalizing the sale of organs, a black market would not be
sustainable.
Another popular opposition to removing the ban is that “a
sales policy would favor the rich over the poor in the procurement
of organs” (Epstein 66).22 While the argument is true,
the rich are already favored over the poor today. Nothing would be
different. The rich
have the ability to instantly go anywhere they want for treatment
while the poor do not.
If more people (despite their financial background) are able
to receive more organs than before and more lives can be saved, then
there is no problem. If
the poor are concerned that the rich would be far more capable of
purchasing organs, then the government could use tax dollars to
purchase those critical organs for the deserving poor. Some opponents of organ sales fear, quite
plausibly, that allowing the sale of organs would give poor people
an incentive to sell their spare
kidney. Preventing poor people
or their families from selling an organ makes them worse off. If organ sales were
legal, some poor people could quickly come up with a down payment on
a house. Even some
middle class people might spring for the cash. In all cases, both buyer and
seller would gain.
Advocates of this
idea do not explain why the poor are misguided in their judgment
that organ selling is in their best interests. The assessment of the
potential harm of losing a kidney as weighed against the potential
benefit of whatever payment is received is, at best, not easy. The risks of hang gliding,
rock climbing or diving from North Sea oil rigs are much greater
than those of the surgery.
It is plausible to say that the expected benefits will be
much greater to the desperately poor who see in selling a kidney the
only hope of making anything of their wretched lives and perhaps
even of surviving, than to the relatively rich. The moral justification for the open
market is that each adult owns his body and thus has the absolute
right to make all decisions regarding it, providing he abstains from
using force or fraud on others. Many find the idea of people
buying and selling human organs in a free market to be repulsive for
any number of reasons.
But those people have no right to use either personal force
or governmental force to stop them, anymore than they have the right
to interfere with their peaceful activities that they judge
repulsive. Some may
need the money for their children or maybe even a car, but it is not
anyone’s right to impose his value system on another. The selling of an
individual’s body parts should be the individual's choice. An individual owns his body
and should be given the choice to make decisions that best reflect
his needs. Not giving
an individual the right to choose about selling his organs imposes
others’ hesitant, biased views on this individual. Legalizing the sale of
organs would give every individual the right to choose, one of the
basic freedoms that the US affords its citizens. As with all peaceful
activities, it is time to end the ban on the purchase and sale of
human organs and to allow a free market, rather than government
officials, to determine who receives transplants. If this is done, not only
will society have regained one of its lost freedoms, it will, at the
same time, be saving thousands of lives that will otherwise be lost
at the altar of government regulation for the public good.
Although
our culture holds that buying and selling organs is highly
distasteful, a good argument for such sales is tentatively being
made. After all,
Americans already sell their blood platelets, eggs, and sperm. This practice is not only
acceptable, but deemed extremely beneficial to society. Financially compensating
donors has made it possible to increase the available supply. Society should learn to
transcend the strong, visceral opposition to organ sales that
functions as the emotional anchor to present policy. Needy recipients currently
wait on endless wait-lists for altruism to reduce the dreadful
shortage of available organs.
Many people are not motivated to donate their organs to
perfect strangers because of the risk involved. It seems that everyone talks
about how desperately organs are needed, but nobody seems to
donate. The current
organ donation system benefits everyone except the donor. Doctors are paid for the
surgery. Recipients are
paid with a kidney.
Hospitals earn profit on the transplant procedure. Doctors and hospitals cannot
be expected to perform transplant surgery with no charge. If everyone gains some kind
of benefit, it is unreasonable to think that a donor should receive
absolutely nothing.
Besides, the donors are the ones that are going through the
surgery voluntarily in order to save someone else. Living donors will require
at least two weeks out of work and have a small amount of increased
health risks. Sure the donor will have the warm, uplifting
feeling associated with helping a fellow man, but this is not enough
of a reward for most people to part with a piece of themselves. In an ideal world the
average person would be altruistic enough to donate a kidney with no
questions asked. The
real world, however, is run by money. We pay men for donating
sperm, and we pay women for donating ova, yet we expect others to
give away an entire organ for no compensation. If the sale of organs were
allowed, people would have more of an incentive to help save the
life of a stranger. Donors must be compensated
for their services.
Altruism has proved time and again not to be sufficient. The affection people have
for their families and intimate friends does not carry over to the
vast world of strangers. The contract of sale, like other
forms of voluntary exchange, is one way to vastly increase available
organs. If there were a
free market for organs, it is an absolute certainty that companies
would sprout up to offer payment to the person's family (or anybody
else that person designated) for his or her organs in the event of a
fatal accident. This would immediately increase the
supply of organs and would, therefore, save countless lives. If a free market prevailed,
there would be no shortage of much-needed organs (which today means
certain death for many), as supply and demand would set the price
that clears the market. It's the ultimate win-win
situation, with money going to the deceased person's beneficiaries
and, at the same time, many lives being saved. The repeated process of
exchange increases the supply of desired goods and directs them to
the individuals who value them most. The current system rests on
a faulty set of assumptions that undermines the intelligence and
rationality of ordinary people. Open markets in organs are
the best available way to enable people with defective organs to get
transplants much more quickly than under the present system. The arguments against
allowing the sale of organs are not compelling, especially when
weighed against the number of lives that would be saved or
significantly improved by the increased supply stimulated by
financial
incentives.
| ||||||||||||||
© 2006 Philosophy
Paradise |